C[hristopher]
C[olumbus] Langdell, SUMMARY of THE LAW OF CONTRACTS, (1871).
1. According to the popular apprehension of the term, a promise is the act of the
promisor alone; but in truth it requires also an act of the promisee. Before any act by
the promisee, the so-called promise is in law only an offer, called by the Romans a
pollicitation. It is not until it is accepted by the promisee that it becomes in law a
promise. A promise in this respect like a gift of property, which is commonly supposed to
be the act of the donor alone, but which requires the acceptance of the donee to pass the
title to the property.
* * *
11. Acceptance has hitherto been considered with reference to such offers only as
contemplate unilateral contracts. When the contract is to be bilateral, though the
principles are the same, the application of them is very different. It still remains true
that the offer requires an acceptance and the giving of the consideration to convert it
into a binding promise; but as the consideration consists of a counter-promise, so the
giving of the consideration is consists in making this counter-promise. It follows also
that the original offer cannot become a binding promise until the counter-promise also
becomes valid and binding, for until then the consideration is not given. Hence the
familiar rules, that in bilateral contracts neither party will be bound unless both are
bound, and that both must become bound at the same moment of time; and these rules hold in
the civil law, and in the law of Scotland, as well as in our law, for, although the former
do not require a consideration to make a promise binding, yet an offer which contemplates
a counter-promise is conditional upon the counter-promise being made.
12. There are other important particulars in which a bilateral contract differs from
one that is unilateral in respect to the acceptance of an offer: while in the latter the
acceptance is merged and lost sight of in the performance of the consideration, in the
former the giving of the consideration is merged and lost sight of in the acceptance;
while in the latter the performance of the consideration necessarily implies an acceptance
of the offer, in the former the acceptance of the offer necessarily implies the giving of
the consideration. Therefore, a mere offer in terms and an acceptance in terms are
sufficient to form a bilateral contract, but not a unilateral contract. So an acceptance
in terms is a sine qua non in a bilateral contract, while in a unilateral contract
an acceptance in terms may be, and commonly is, dispensed with. Again in a unilateral
contract the offer becomes a contract in consequence of what the offeree does, in a
bilateral contract in consequence of what he says. The reason why an acceptance in
terms is necessary, and why it also suffices, in a bilateral contract, is, that what is
called an acceptance is in that connection also and chiefly a counter-promise.
13. But how is it, the reader may ask, that a mere offer on one side and an acceptance
of it on the other can create a promise on each side? that what purports to be but one
offer and one acceptance is in effect two offers and two acceptances? It is because
everything except the original offer and the acceptance of it is implied. Thus, it
generally appears from the nature and terms of an offer whether it requires a
counter-offer, and, if it does, what the terms of such counter-offer must be; and
therefore nothing need be said in the offer upon either of those points. Nor is it ever
necessary for an offerer to say that he will accept a counter-offer, if made; for if his
offer requires a counter-offer, it is necessarily implied that he will accept the latter.
So the acceptance of an offer which requires a counter-offer need say nothing about the
latter, and the terms of the latter, having been fixed by the original offer, do not need
to be repeated. Then, the counter-offer being thus made by implication, no further act of
acceptance of it is necessary, for, the original offerer having by implication declared
his intention to accept it, he is conclusively presumed to remain in that state of mind so
long as his offer continues; and hence the counter-offer, by a conclusive presumption of
law, is accepted the moment it is made. The same principle is familiar in transfers of
property; for, while the acceptance of the transferee is necessary for the passing of the
title, yet it may be, and frequently is, given in advance by soliciting the transfer.
14. It has been seen that the acceptance of the original offer, in the case of a
bilateral contract, must be expressed, i.e., must be made by words or signs; and
that the reason for this is, that the acceptance contains a counter-offer. Moreover, the
reason why the counter-offer makes it necessary that the acceptance should be expressed
is, that communication to the offeree is of the essence of every offer. The acceptance,
therefore, must be communicated to the original offerer, and until such communication the
contract is not made. When the parties are together and contract orally, no question can
often arise as to communication; but when they are at a distance from each other and
contract by letter, such a question frequently arises. The principles, however, is the
same in both cases. In contracts inter pręsentes the words or signs must be both
heard or seen and understood; in contracts inter absentes the letter must be
received and read. Upon this latter point, however, there has been much difference of
opinion, and it has been supposed to be pretty well settled in England and this country
that the contract is complete the moment the letter of acceptance is mailed. Most of the
authority on the subject, however, consists of dicta, and these dicta may be
explained by the fact that the nature of the question has been misunderstood. Of actual
decision there is indeed very little. Of all the cases contained in the writers
collection of Cases on Contracts, the point in question seems to have been decided in only
three, one of them (and the earliest) a Massachusetts case (McCulloch v. the Eagle
Ins. Co.), another a New York Case (Vassar v. Camp ), and the third a Scotch case
(Thomson v. James). All the other cases turned upon some other question. Thus, in
Adams v Lindsell, it was erroneously supposed that the offer had been revoked
between the mailing and the receipt of the letter of acceptance (181), and hence
that the case depended upon the time when the acceptance became complete. The only real
question, however, was whether the acceptance came too late, the letter containing the
offer having miscarried. In Potter v. Sanders, the contract with Potter was
entitled to priority in any view, since the Statute of frauds was not satisfied as to the
contract with Coates until April 17, and though the latter contract might relate back to
the oral agreement as between the parties to it, it could not so relate as to a third
person. In Dunlop v. Higgins, the only question was whether the offer was accepted
in time; and it was held that it was, whether the acceptance became complete on the
mailing or on the receipt of the letter of acceptance. In Hebbs Case, in Br. and Am.
Tel. Co. v. Colson, and in Harriss Case, the contract was unilateral (6),
and hence those cases are not in point. In McCulloch v. Eagle Ins. Co. the question
was actually involved, and the decision was in favor of the view here contended for. In
Mactier v. Frith, the offer was to sell to Mactier an undivided half-interest in a
cargo of brandy already in his possession. As soon, therefore, as Mactier accepted the
brandy on the terms offered, the title passed, and he became indebted for the price. No
actual promise by him was necessary. It was not even necessary that he should write a
letter of acceptance, still less that it should reach Frith. In Averill v. Hedge,
the only question confessedly was whether the letter of acceptance was mailed in time. In
Tayloe v. Merchants Fire Ins. Co. defendants offer contemplated a
unilateral contract, and this offer was accepted and the consideration paid the moment
when the plaintiff sent his check for the premium. It was the same as if money had been
sent. It is true that the plaintiff became liable to the defendant on his check, but that
liability arose when the check was delivered, i.e. when the letter containing it
was mailed. Vassar v. Camp must be admitted to be in point, but the effect of the
decision was not such as to recommend it. Indeed, it is doubtful if it can stand in any
view that can be take of it; for, assuming that the contract was complete the moment the
plaintiffs letter of acceptance was mailed, there is much ground for holding that
the defendants liability was conditional upon their receiving prompt notice of the
acceptance of their offer. This view may be fairly rested upon a necessary implication,
though it is much aided by expressions in the defendants offer. It also detracts
from the authority of Vassar v. Camp, that the court regarded the question as
already conclusively settled by Mactier v. Firth. Dunmore v. Alexander is
opposed to Vassar v. Camp, so far as it goes, but the point was not involved.
Thomson v. James agrees with Vassar v. Camp, but the reasoning by which the
decision is supported is at least neutralized by the dissenting opinion of Lord
Curriehill. The case of S. v. F. contains a powerful argument by Merlin in support
of the view adopted by McCulloch v. The Eagle Ins. Co., but the point was not
decided.
15. It remains to notice the principal arguments which have been advanced in support of
the view that the contract is complete the moment the letter of acceptance is mailed. 1.
It is said that, if the contract is not made until the letter of acceptance comes to the
knowledge of the offerer, it can never be made. This proposition assumes that, if the
contract cannot be made until the acceptance comes to the knowledge of the offerer, it
must be because this knowledge of the offerer is one of the necessary elements of a
contract. If the argument be stated in the form of a syllogism, it will stand thus: If the
contract must become known to the offeree the moment it is made; it must equally become
known to the offeree the moment it is made; but a contract inter absentes cannot
become known to both parties at the same moment, and so not at the moment it is made; ergo
need not become known to the offerer the moment it is made. The fault of this syllogism is
in the major premise, which is untrue. The reason why the contract must become known to
the offerer the moment it is made is an accidental one; namely, because the contract is
made the moment the counter-offer is made, and the counter-offer is made the moment the
letter of acceptance comes to the knowledge of the offeree. 2. It is said that an offer
made through the mail impliedly authorizes an answer to be sent through the same channel;
and therefore, when the offeree has mailed a letter of acceptance, he has done everything
which the offer requires him to do. It is true that he has done everything required of him
as to the mode of communicating his counter-offer; but the offer also requires by a
necessary implication that a counter-offer shall be made, and this cannot be done without
communication. If, therefore, the offer should expressly declare that the contract should
be complete immediately upon mailing a letter of acceptance, such a declaration would be
wholly inoperative. 3. It is said that the offerer, by sending his offer by mail, makes
the post-office his servant or messenger to receive and return an answer, and therefore
that the mailing of an answer is a delivery of it to the offerer. It is unnecessary to
question the correctness of this proposition, for it may be fully admitted, without at all
advancing the argument in support of which it is adduced. Even if the offerer should send
his offer by his own servant, and the latter should bring back a letter of acceptance,
though the delivery of the letter of acceptance to the servant would be a delivery to his
master, and so vest the property in the letter in the master, it would not complete the
contract. If, indeed, the offerer should send his offer by a messenger, and should
authorize the latter to receive a verbal acceptance as the offerers agent, the case
would be different; for the communication of the acceptance to the agent would be a
communication of it to the principal, and the knowledge of the agent would be the
knowledge of the principal. 4. It has been claimed that the purposes of substantial
justice, and the interests of contracting parties as understood by themselves, will be
best served by holding that the contract is complete the moment the letter of acceptance
is mailed; and cases have been put to show that the contrary view would produce not only
unjust but absurd results. The true answer to this argument is, that it is irrelevant;
but, assuming it to be relevant, it may be turned against those who use it without losing
any of its strength. The only cases of real hardship are where there is a miscarriage of
the letter of acceptance, and in those cases a hardship to one of the parties is
inevitable. Adopting one view, the hardship consists in making one liable on a contract
which he is ignorant of having made; adopting the other view, it consists in depriving one
of the benefit of a contract which he supposes he has made. Between these two evils the
choice would seem to be clear: the former is positive, the latter merely negative; the
former imposes a liability to which no limit can be placed, the latter leaves everything in
statu quo. As to making provision for the contingency of the miscarriage of a letter,
this is easy for the person who sends it, while it is practically impossible for the
person to whom it is sent.
EOD |